The Biology of the Mind


Humans are animals. If we want to understand ourselves, we should understand them.
Active embodiment and "scenes", or object-and-action schemas are the keys to this.


Plan for this Lecture
arguments for the identity of human and animal minds
what evolutionary explanations tell about both
animal intentionality is the world of actions
active embodiment is the source of mental content
coming to a general picture of cognition


1. Arguments for the Identity of Human and Animal Mind

1.1. The Biological Function of Intelligence and its Characterization
In general:
    Sensorimotor adaptation - not necessarily only in the sense of optimality...
More closely:
    Successful coordination of biological actions.
                "Coordination" is a tricky word here - it anticipates our later conclusion that much of high-level intelligence is based on low-level one.
                 For instance, having preexsiting primitive actions is important; the rest is just to put them together, to "co-ordinate" them, in a minimalist sense.

In detail: 1.2. and 1.3.

1.2. Human Behavior Serves Biological Function
Explanatory illustration: an "anecdote" taken from a famous book.
Emmanuele Le Roy Ladurie: "Montaillou" (New York: Vintage, 1979)

Peasants in 13. century France spent much of their time just scratching - as baboons do ("grooming").
(in fact not anecdote a revealing story from microhistory and its coupling to a known ethological fact about primates)

            About "Montaillou"
            "This book tells the story of the 14th century villagers and peasants of Montaillou. It chronicles their everyday lives,
                 its importance is far greater than the story of the Cathar heresy, it is the story of the kind of people that are usually
                forgotten to history."

                "love and marriage, gestures and emotions, conversations and gossip, clans and factions, crime and violence, concepts of time
                and space, attitudes to the past, animals, magic and folklore, death and beliefs about the other world."


1.3. What the Mind of an Organism is for
        "Elephants Don't Play Chess" (R. Brooks). Nor did humans when they acquired minds.
         
Sensory input occurs in the biological context:
        in meaningful situations of complex nature
        not raw input but based on co-existence and mutual interaction
Remember the notion of language game - this is also a "game"
Perhaps the least unit is a meaningful complex of actions
We will resolve the holistic "situation" of this "game" into composites: origin of mechanisms, origin of logic, origin of narratives.

1.4. Same Function - Same Structure
Animal and human minds serve the same biological functions and operate among the same essential circumstances.
Is it the same mind? We have to look into evolution to see what kind of mind it is (and this will supply more details
on why to believe in the identity).


2. What Evolutionary Explanations Tell About the Mind

2.1. The Nature of Evolutionary Explanation
Search for the distal causes of behavior control
Note Mayr's distinction between proximal (= immediate, close) and distal (= past, remote) causes in evolution
Example for distal cause is adaptation.
A well-known application of this principle is sociobiology and evolutionary psychology
They have an exaggerated focus on adaptation.

(2.2. The Positive Message from all Evolutionary Explanations

Psychological properies are biological properties, which have a history.
History can explain the biological basis and function of cognition.
....This picture of the mind is usually completely ignored (not even denied!) in mainstream knowledge & mind theory.)

2.3. What is Evolution if not Adaptation

Adaptation is an extremely (!) important but NOT a universal evolutionary feature.
Three universal evolutionary features: unity, embodiment, entrenchment.
Unity, def:                      All animals are similar in all traits, the closer relatives the better. A consequence of evolutionary continuity.
Embodiment, def.:         The input of the mind is what the body produces when interacting with the environment
Entrenchment, def.:        Old systems are "buried" under new ones, and impossible to change.



2.4. Unity (works both ways)
Species exist in philogenetic continuity.
Therefore,
(1) Most human traits must exist in animals.
(2) Most animal traits must exist in man.

Both are big conceptual steps forward - (1) the lifting of animals to humans (2) the lowering of man to animals.
There is a temptation to believe that typical human cognitive abilities are very high-level and specific to us,
and to believe at the same time, that animal abilities are low level ones.
Unity shows that it cannot be that way.
         This is a very simple point which is overlooked so often.
            Of course this point could be elaborated in detail.

         The argument from unity assumes gradualism of all traits, for instance.
         In a more elaborate treatment we should consider philogenetic mechanisms etc., but that does not change much.


2.5. Entrenchment

I.e. The burying of old systems
The metaphor: layers of sand and soil and debris.... as in archeology    (W. Wimsatt)
                    Schank, J. C., and W. C. Wimsatt, 1988.  Generative entrenchment and evolution.
                            In: A. Fine and P. K. Machamer, eds., PSA-1986, vol. 2. East Lansing: The Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 33-60.


What is buried away cannot change later, bacause it is no more accessible for change.
Less metaphorically: all mutationsare  devastating because of avalanche-like cumulative effects.

If we find an old system in humans, it must be exactly (!) the same in even distant animals.
(Of course here we use the fact that historical distance implies present-day distance).

Much of the human cognitive systems is old.
Therefore, the human system must be identical with the old animal systems which we
find in distant species today.
                            There is an important side issue here. The concept of entrenchment is a developmental
                                    one, and it does not directly apply to immediate gene products. So the well-known
                                    examples for "molecular clocks in evolution" (
changes at a steady rate) do not contradict the argument.

How do we know that human cognitive systems are old?
        There are various justifications of this notion. Such as:
        Examples from complex physiological adaptations. E.g. sneezing.
Sneezing is an old system found in many mammals.
        It always produces the same typical pattern: eyes shut, hight muscle tone, etc.
        From entrenchment we understand that one feature cannot be changed later.
        Therefore, speezing must also produce the same chilly feeling in dogs and cats etc.
This is not the best example for cognition (sneezing is not very smart eh?) but it is vey compellig.
        A better (but less dramatic) example is social facilitation in dogs.
        Dogs can spontaneously learn pointing and eye-following.
        This has a twis, as dogs are human products selected for human-like features.
        Why is the story relevant, then?
        (1) But they remained very distant relatives to humans.
        If they - with some evolutrionary modifications - can learn these, then the same basic system
        of interpretation is there in the mind since the common ancestors of dog and man.
        (2) Knock-down argument: but dogs are still animals, arent't they?
        So probably other animals are capable of the same, with a little breeding help from man.

Another (and, again, more dramatic) example will be discussed with in relationship to "agency".


2.6. Evolutionary Embodiment

The basis:
Genotype - phenotype (replicator - interactor). Every evolutionary interaction is based on the phenotpye.
The phenotype defines boundary conditions of interaction (in the air, in the water, on the soil etc).
There is no "environment" in the abstract sense - note that historically the word "Umwelt" (von Uexkull) reflects this.
The crosspoint of environment and mind (or gene) is the actually existing body.
Mental content cannot be (is not) a "representation" of environment as something completely idependent
    mental content consists of utilization recipes for the available joint features of the enviroment and the body.

It is the body where meaning resides, if seen on the evolutionary context.
Language and other concepts "plug in" into ready-made meanings available from philogenetically earlier times.
Such meaning must be non-verbal, non-conceptual, at least backwards from some point of evolutionary history
            (Much research is done these days on embodiment and "non-conceptual content" etc. so part
            of this is fairly standard material - up to the point where I will speak of active embodiment)


NCC:
Definitions vary, but all writers agree on this: a mental state's content is non-conceptual if an organism can be in
that state without having to possess the concepts used in canonically characterizing that state's content.


"What is Non-Conceptual Content?
" http://www.cogs.susx.ac.uk/users/ronc/whatis-ncc.html
A bibliography of non-conceptual content http://www.cogs.susx.ac.uk/users/ronc/ncc-bibliography.htm

More about embodiment comes below.


3. Inside the Animal Mind
the strongest pillars are these: inborn intentionality; intentionality is coupled to agency; animal agency detection

3.1. Intentionality
Intentionality, definition: beliefs, desires etc and their attribution
            (one of the evergreens of cognitive science, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-intentionality/
             http://www.u.arizona.edu/~chalmers/biblio.html; in particular http://www.u.arizona.edu/~chalmers/biblio/2.html)

There is a vast amount of evidence about the existence of animal intentionality, with details unclear.
            consciousness tests http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-animal/; http://www.u.arizona.edu/~chalmers/biblio/6.html#6.4c
            imitation (social facilitation), viewpoint taking (e.g. triangulation), animal lies (misguiding behavior)
            naming (categorization plus "rigid designator") and more.....
             - adaptation, teleology, D.C. Dennett: The Intentional Stance (1987), Cambridge MA, MIT Press; http://cognet.mit.edu/MITECS/Entry/dennett
             - a comprehesive treatment of the full range: Allan and Beckoff: Species of Mind  full text

Important, however:
Intentionality's roots are inborn in humans (Meltzoff; Gergely and Watson)
            Meltzoff early imitation experiments showed that already newborns have "social" mental competence
                    description of the Meltzoff experiments.
            Gergely and Watson show that 3 months old infants have firm expectations about actions
                    description of the Gergely and Watson experiments

The apparent basis of early intentionality of the latter type is the use of built-in contingency detectors (Gergely):
            stimuli with high contingency (high reliablity) are preferred in age 0-3 month;
            low contingency (random) is ignored both then and later;
            interest switches to medium contingency at 3 months
medium contingency is typical for "agents" (actors) with voluntary actions (autonomy)

To sum up: intentionality reduces to agency and has a clear evolutionary origin ("inborn" means this).
                A remark. In developmental psychology a conceptually more refined picture is used.
                    The relationship between (early) intentionality and agency is a matter of ongoing debate.
                    The typical view is that intentionality is part of the "self" concept and agency also, but the
                        two are not directly related (there is an indirect relation throught the self).



3.2. Agency, definition
Agents: actors, pro-active entities, have the ability to initiate action;
agents are movers (cf. what moves what).


3.3. Agency detection by animals
This is a hard problem, since movers and the moved parts are highly correlated
        Perhaps contingency is a cue, again.
        The theoretical explanation for agency detection is not known yet.
The empirical facts, however, are well-studied - in dogs and cats, for instance.
Dogs are able to launch tennis ball by their nose upon observing humans doing it by hand                             (pictures pending)
Cats open doors by jumping up and pulling the door-handle, upon observing humans turning it                         (picture pending)


3.4. Objects and Actions in Animal Life
It appears that the basic elements of the animal mental world are objects and actions.
Is this perhaps a self-evident truth? What else could they be?
In actuality, it is far from being a safe and/or simple statement, but it can be risked.
    Objects - it is generally assummed / accepted that animals (i.e. higher animals) partition their environment into objects
            (for instance, every study on animal intentionality and agency uses this as an unproblematic fact).
    Actions - we just discussed that actions are performed by agents, and agents are not easy to define or identify.

            In fact both finding objects and findig the agents in the environment are difficult problems for robotics,
            even if it is assumed
that these are important.

Objects are special integrative wholes, and actions similarly so.
Instead of dealing with their sensory and neural backgrounds, we will focus on these questions:

            what properties of the environment make object - and - action thinking possible?
            how does object - and - action thinking work?
            what consequences are there for the structure of the animal and human mind?



3.5. The 'Scene' Theory: Dynamic Situations
In particular, we can ask about the relationship between festures of the structure of environment and features of mind.
The remarks here will be rudimentary and hypothetical.
I put forward a scene theory which combines many elements that are already at hand.

Adult animals (and humans) organize their perceptual fields into scenes (plots, scripts, situations, sessions...)

Scene = an interactive bevavior complex, which involves a goal (or a main motif), some actor(s) and actions, objects, and
            spatial as well as temporal elements.

A scene is the least contiguous unit for mental activity (---- > this will be captured in the notion of mental models)

Evidence for the "scene" theory
            Tolman's expectation theory                            (animals anticipate sensory input as part of a larger unit)
            Thorndike's ecological selection theory            (animals select relevant signals in the environment on an ecological basis; not anything is a signal)
            The "verb" theory of dog behavior                   (dogs - and other animals - take words not as names but as 'verbs' relative to behavior complexes)




4. Embodiment and Active Embodiment
Embodiment is one of the big stories of the nineties:
How the mind uses the body, and how the body is reflected in the mind.

Wheeler, M. (1997): Cognition's Coming Home: The Reunion of Life and Mind, in:
P. Husbands és I. Harvey szerk.: Fourth European Conference on Artificial Life,
MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
ftp://ftp.cogs.susx.ac.uk/pub/ecal97/online/F035.ps.gz

Sometimes there is a spiritual or existentialist turn here:
http://www.bodywisdom.org/pages/embod.html



4.1. The Robotics Version
Intelligence without representation - simple agents perform directional operations using their body
No description, no "mind" (in the classical sense), only action control ("Cambrian intelligence").

http://www.ai.mit.edu/people/brooks/publications.shtml

Brooks, R. A., (1986), Achieving artificial intelligence through building robots, MIT A. I. Memo No. 899.
Brooks, R. A., (1991a), New approaches to robotics, Science, 253 , 1227–1232.
Brooks, R. A., (1991b), Intelligence without reason. Proceedings of IJCAI–91, 569–595,
Brooks, R. A. és Stein, L. A. (1993), „Building brains for bodies”, MIT A. I. Memo No. 1439.
Brooks, R.A., Breazeal, C., Irie, R., Kemp, C.C., Marjanovic, M., Scassellati, B.,Williamson, M. (1998): Alternate Essences of Intelligence, Proc. AAAI-98
Brooks, R.A, Breazeal, C., Marjanovic, M., Scassellati, M., Williamson, M. (1998): The Cog Project: Building a Humanoid Robot, in: (C. Nehaniv, C. szerk.)
    Computation for Metaphors, Analogy and Agents, Vol. 1562, Springer Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, Springer-Verlag, New York.


4.2. Beyond Robotics: Coordination Revisited

Brooks et al: embodiment reduces to "action selection".
From the persepctive of cognitive ethology of higher animals, this is not cognition itself but the 'raw material' for that.
Cognition is coordination, but it is not jut reactive.


4.3. The Meaning of Embodiment for Cognition
A bodily basis for the mental.

Example: The Theory of Metaphor (Lakoff and Johnson)
                Lakoff, G. (1987): Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things, Chicago UP, Chicago, IL.
                Lakoff, G. és Johnson, M. (1980): Metaphors We Live By, Chicago UP, Chicago, IL.
                Johnson, M. (1987): The Body in the Mind, Chicago UP, Chicago, IL.
Annotated Bibliography of Metaphor and Cognitive science
Center for the Cognitive Science of Metaphor, Online

The basic idea: a small number of fundamental image schemas (Gestalt) bear all meaning in language ----> all meaning in the mind

Container
 Balance
 Full-Empty
 Iteration
Compulsion
Blockage
Counterforce
Process
 Surface
Restraint Removal
Enablement
Attraction
Matching
Part-Whole
Mass-Count
Path
Link
Collection
Contact
Center-Periphery
Cycle
Splitting
Merging
Object
Scale
                         Table: The partial list of image schemata from Johnson (1987)

Metaphor = figurative use of basic schemas (e.g. into, in, prevent, etc etc)
George Lakoff: The Contemporary Theory of Metaphor, full text here


4.4. Active Embodiment
The situated/embodied picture is based on sensorimotor notions, yet sometimes the resulting image of the mind is passive.
For instance, a focus on experience puts the mind in the position of a static observer; things happen to the owner of this mind.

Most image schemas of Johnson are just descriptive, even if (as in the case of force) this is not obvious at the first glance.
Perhaps garden-path and a few others are exceptions. But even these are more contemplative trhan not.
The fundamental schemas of action, such as an if.... then schema are completely missing.

Work in cognitive developmental psychology on the origin of embodied concepts somewhat changes this situation.
Thelen et al characterize "force embodiment" as a concept resulting from cycles of repeated proactivity and related experience.
The "scene" theory extends this into a general framework of active embodiment, where perception-action cycles organized
into meaningful units play the fundamental role.


5. Coming to a General Picture

5.1. The Strategy from Here

Knowledge of Animals
Thinking without words; a model of the animal mind
A pre-wired world, consisting objects and organisms, as source of animal knowledge.
Body skills and their use in cognition.

The Everyday World
No knowledge without prior knowledge
Everyday realism, folk ontology, folk psychology.
The reliable world as human and animal legacy
Mechanisms as simplified causal schemes.

Rationality in Action
Rationality's basic form: goal-consistent action plan.
Abstract knowledge as based on action: the active mind.

etc/

5.2. Relationship with Human Knowledge; Backflash to Lecture Two.

Wittgenstein is so special not because no one can argue against it.
(In fact many philosophers, including Kripke, Putnam, and the new analitics do that.)\
That is just part of the usual game of philosophy.

But Wittgenstein's significance is different: it's the only philosophical picture of the mind
    that is compatible with philogenetic continuity: unity, embodiment and entrenchment.

            Remark:
                Here it will be important to ask how certain our knowledge about evolution is.
                That could be the topic of another lecture.
                The answer, in short, is this: very certain - in fact as certain as you can get.



5.3. Summary: the "Discovery" of Animals

Cognitive science is now in the process of (re)discovering animals.
But: Native Americans don't like to hear that they were "discovered" by Columbus... and if animals had abstract
concepts, they would probably raise the same objection.
Animals were always in front of our eyes.
More than just that, humans have always lived together with animals - the dog is about as old as man.
Breeders and keepers have treated animals in everyday interaction and accummulated evidence on animal minds.

(cf. The meaning of history: compare selected writers to what large numbers of people think/know in a period.
Microsociology/microhistory - another revolution in the making...)

Motto:

Darwin grounded evolution theory on what every breeder knew but no philosopher did.
Cognitive science can ground the theory of mind in the same way.